My Argument in Brief

We think and speak in declarative sentences. Each declaration proclaims a truth, and every truth is built upon some support, a warrant, that we think makes it true. That warrant in its turn is based upon some worldview, an axiom that we accept as a given and would never consider questioning in the ordinary blur of daily life. So the truths that well up into our minds and gush forth from our lips (and everybody else’s) are only the pointy tip of the pyramid.

In times of consensus, these truth claims go unexamined for the very good reason that no one bothers to question them. But when agreement collapses, conflicting claims to truth and goodness must appeal to a warrant acceptable to all disputants. And when both the truth of our claims and the warrants that support them fall into general dispute, cultures enter unsettling periods of contention that can only be resolved when disputants agree to new warrants with which to examine their claims to truth, goodness, and beauty.

Western culture has seen two such breakdowns in the last five hundred years.

Historians call the first and more cataclysmic one the Protestant Reformation (1517-1688). Authority, a warrant built upon a trust in the truth and goodness of some higher power, had served as the final arbiter of all disputes in the thousand years after the fall of Rome. For all the violence of the Middle Ages, legitimacy remained rooted in the consensual acceptance of a hierarchical order with God as its guarantor. The collapse of that order was especially brutal for two reasons. First, authority had mortared over the patchwork of competing powers that had preserved some remnants of civilized life in the Dark Ages. Its loss unleashed an explosion of dissension. Those tensions were disastrously magnified by a second problem, a peculiarity in the nature of authority as warrant. Because it was built upon the trust of its adherents for its power, when that trust was revoked, competing authorities found themselves with no means to resolve their conflicting claims to truth and goodness. As Catholic battled Lutheran and moderate fought radical, and sect warred upon sect within them, disputants found no common authority to resolve their conflicting claims to truth and goodness. Trust faltered, failed, and dissolved, and all the interlocking layers of social and political authority found themselves teetering on the abyss of total rejection.

This crisis gave birth to modernism, which supplanted medievalism over a dismal and bloody two centuries of groping for a warrant consensually acceptable to the warring factions. What finally came into focus was reliance by individuals on reason and  examined experience as imperfect replacement axioms to replace lost trust. This shift also required a shift in moral agency from authority to the thinking minds of persons who now must examine experience for their own warrants and negotiate those in their relations with others. The nature of that reason and the reliability of that experience has posed a continuing riddle ever since . Four specific means gradually allowed individuals to subject their experience to rational scrutiny : empiricism (which only gradually became modern science), inductive and deductive reason , expertise, and undifferentiated experience. While these truth tests proved superior to authority in one respect — they allowed individuals to examine their declarations and gradually improve their reliability– they could never offer the lost certainty of authority or provide the same level of consensus because they relied on individual reason and private experience. This difference explains why medievalism seems incredibly remote to the modern mind, but in some persons uncomfortable with the tentativeness of science and the subjectivity of the other modern truth tests, the magisterial voice of authority still provokes a powerful nostalgia.

The second great crisis was both slower and deeper. The discontents of modernism emerged strongly in the Romantic movement of the nineteenth century. It was fueled by the birth of popular culture that magnified the hypocrisies and inadequacies of modernist warrants. Awareness of these failures built gradually, at least until the turn of the twentieth century. World War I brought modernism to the same point of crisis that medievalism suffered in the Reformation. But what alternative warrants could survive a frank analysis of that war, “western civilization’s attempt to commit suicide”? The frantic search produced a whirlwind of novelty in the first two decades of the twentieth century. A new and furious intellectual scavenger hunt had begun.

The solution required rejecting not only modernism but even the more basic axiom that had supported both modernism and medievalism. This was the assumption that any correct response to reality must correspond to it in some reflective way. This correspondence theory had formed the foundation of all earlier claims to truth, but modernism hacked upon its very root as it chopped away at the reliability of private perception and our reasoning about it. On what grounds could truth, goodness, and beauty be built if not their relationship to external reality?

The answer to that question was cobbled together using bits and pieces of the intellectual criticism modernism had endured from its beginnings. A clear theory only emerged in the 1970’s after a half-century of shrill cultural contention waged against modernism by conservatives nostalgic for the loss certainty of authority and radicals keenly aware of the inconsistencies of the modern warrant. The new view was postmodernism, and its novel means of resolution was simply to cut off truth and goodness claims from any need for external verification. No reality was necessary other than an individually created one, and no common reasoning was required to make sense of private experience. But some filtering mechanism must discriminate among a torrent of conflicting truth and goodness claims. The postmodern means of warranting this virtual circle of individually assembled truths was their internal consistency rather than any correspondence to externals. The individual had been the source of truth for the modernists, so why not take that axiom all the way? Why not give power and weight to whatever the individual chose to value: intuition, insight, imagination, emotion, dreams, unconscious desires, strongly held beliefs, or myth? Philosophy called such an internal schema coherentism, but the cadre of mostly French intellectuals who defined postmodernism as a theory added a brilliant twist to the older notion, considering culture itself to be a source and measure of coherence, thus giving rise to an identity politics that requires no justification beyond abstaining from hypocrisy to achieve consistency…and therefore truth.

By the turn of the 21st century, the defects of such a view began to come into focus, for cultures in postmodern theory could no more find means to resolve conflict than could the individuals who compose them, leading to an obsession with power structures and an intractable clash of moral disputants reminiscent of the worst impasses of the Reformation. Modernism continues to offer its own warrant, shorn of some but not all of its more offensive errors. And authority continues to lure at least some persons to its comforting certainties despite the hostility of both modernists and postmodernists and the loss of its appeal in an age of cultural diversity.

All of this is history. But the shredding of consensus that is history’s legacy exacts its contemporary price. It requires us to go beyond simple declarations of what is true, what is good, and what is beautiful and beyond the reasons for them, for we face no consensus that gives them force. The simplest terms we use to make our truth claims have been compromised. They depend for their meaning on the axioms we adopt and the kind of warrant we embrace as we speak them, any of which our listener might not share at that moment, that we ourselves might reverse without compunction in the next moment. Being attentive to warrant complicates our declarations, but it also restores their meaning. The alternative is to thrust all declarations concerning truth, goodness, and beauty into cacophony.

Advertisements